Introduction to Legal Theory

Primer to Jurisprudence (Legal Theory)

Outline
  1. Aims of Legal Theory
  2. Legal Positivism: Laws and the Legal System
  3. Legal Anti-Positivism: The Critique of Positivism
  4. Legal Anti-Positivism: Hard Cases
  5. The Natural Law Tradition

1. Aims of Legal Theory

  • To produce intellectual backbone to law by distinguishing it from similar phenomena such as coercion, authority and morality.
  • To provide good reasons – beyond the formal legal rules – to justify the resolution of legal disputes.
  • To describe, justify, evaluate, criticise or reform the law.

Why do we need legal theory?

Certain legal theorists have raised the question ‘why do we need legal theory’. HLA Hart, for instance, questioned the need for legal theory when other equally practical disciplines like medicine do not raise the question of what is medicine? Hart’s assumption is that if practice can go well without asking lofty philosophical questions, why do we need these theories at all? The following two justifications suffice the controversy regarding the need for legal theory.

  1. Law and Bus-Driving

MacCormick draws a parallel between bus-driving and lawyering as both pertain to the practice of a certain profession. He argues that as we do not need philosophy of bus-driving, likewise we do not need theory for law. But we need to draw a distinction between bus-driving and lawyering. Unlike bus-driving, law is comprehensive in its regulatory reach, and where it chooses not to interfere, this is due to self-restraint. For instance, constitutional guarantee of freedom of speech is an illustration of law’s exercise of self-restraint. Moreover, whereas bus-driving is optional, law is non-optional. This means that no one can opt-out of the application of law. It compulsorily claims to apply to all those who fall within its self-defined jurisdiction.

  1. Role of Coercion in Law

According to Kelsen, law is a coercive order which is common to all legal systems. This coercion can be serious. It may imprison a person or take his life and property. There is a debate amongst theorists regarding the centrality of coercion in law. But all theorists agree that coercion is a significant aspect of law.

What does all this add up to? Does this mean that since law affects us deeply, therefore, we need justification for law? Some theorists argue that because of this reason, law needs justification. Once it is settled that law needs justification, another issue arises: what kind of legal theory do we need?

What kind of legal theory do we need? Justificatory, critical, reforming or descriptive?

Justificatory task:

This approach centres on the justifications of law in the society. Dworkin argues that the law justifies the exercise of coercive power by the state. He asserts that the best legal theory is that which provides the best explanation for the exercise of coercive power of the state. Finnis who has put new life in natural law, argues that his book would explain how law is justified. He argues that the moral purpose of the law and the aspiration to achieve a common good for everyone justifies the existence of law in society.

“There are human goods that can be secured only through the institutions of human law…. It is in the object of this book to identify those goods… and thus to show how and on what conditions such institutions are justified….”[1]

An alternative view of the task of legal theory: General and Descriptive account of law

Hart was a philosopher and a barrister. He wanted to re-infuse legal theory with philosophy. Hart’s The Concept of Law is based on his lectures to undergraduate students. His alternative view is that legal theory should be general and descriptive

In the introduction to The Concept of Law, he provided the general and descriptive conception of law; it is an important preliminary to any useful moral criticism of law. It does not mean that he is not interested in moral dimension of law. Such dimension is of secondary importance in Hart’s conception of law. Ronald Dworkin, who was his successor at Oxford, subjected Hart’s conception of law to criticism. Dworkin provided a justificatory and evaluative theory of law which was criticised by Hart in his postscript. Hart did not answer the criticism on his work himself. After his death, unfinished documents were found which paved the way to provide rebuttal to the criticism of his work especially by Dworkin.

Whether justification and description are mutually exclusive?
It is important to note that the justificatory task does not necessarily have to be in opposition to other approaches such as descriptive, evaluative, critical and reformist. There may exist an overlap between them; for instance, justificatory approach can be adopted while being critical and reformist simultaneously.

Having reviewed the approaches to study legal theory, it is pertinent to now look over the very subject matter of this study. If jurisprudence is descriptive, what does it describe? The obvious answer would be: law. But what does actually constitute law and how can efforts be made to describe it? Whether is it even worth an attempt to define the law? These are the questions that would now be looked over in the following sections through different theoretical lenses provided by John Austin, Hans Kelsen, HLA Hart, Ronald Dworkin, Raz and Finnis.

2. Legal Positivism: Laws and the Legal System

Hart does not define law, rather he provides answers to three recurrent issues. In the first chapter of his work, he mentions these issues, which are:

1.      How does law differ from, and how is it related to, orders backed by threats?

The difference between law and bus-driving shows that law is non-optional and coercive. Not everyone is obliged to learn the skill of bus-driving. On the other hand, obeying the law is an obligation on everyone. Orders backed by a gunman are still different from law. Non-compliance with the orders of a gunman may lead to bad consequences; however, this cannot be equated with the sanctions of the law. Some argue that state is the biggest bully of all. For Hart, it is the authority that brings compliance based on its efficacy. However, according to Austin, it is the threat of sanction that brings obedience.

2.   How does legal obligation differs from, and how is it related to, moral obligation?

This is a big question. Morality also comes to us in normative form. It also tells us what to do and what not to do. There must be some relation between law and morality because they share certain features.

3.   What are rules, and to what extent is law an affair of rules?

Hart uses the technique of contrasting law with the phenomena (threats and morality), which has ostensible similarities with it in order to paint a more sophisticated picture of its distinctive features.

Legal Positivism: A Brief Introduction

Bentham, Austin and Hart are legal positivists. According to them, law exists when it is posited, or laid down, by some person or procedure. Legal positivists sought to define what law is rather than what it ought to be. For example, it is often contested whether abortion is illegal. Law prohibits abortion under the UK Abortion Act 1967. This Act is passed by the parliament. This law is valid because of its sources, and not because of its merits. In other words, the Abortion Act 1967 is a law because it is passed by the parliament. It does not matter whether abortion itself is good or bad.

We should not over-emphasise this thesis by saying that legal positivists deny moral views. Positivists argue that what makes law is its source, not its merits. There is a separation between law and morality according to positivists because of their origins. But on many points, they believe in both law and morality, and recognize the overlap between the two.[2]

Command Theories of Legal Positivism

John Austin describes law as a command. For Austin, law is a command by a political superior – the Sovereign – to the political inferior who habitually obeys it and is backed by a threat of sanction. This is a useful idea from a common man’s perspective. Obey the law or go to jail!

Concepts arising from this definition:

1. Command, 2. Sovereign, 3. Habitual Obedience, and 4. Sanction (the smallest chance of incurring the smallest possible evil)

Who is a Sovereign?
According to Austin, someone is a sovereign if the bulk of society habitually obeys him. His power is absolute, unlimited and indivisible. Everyone obeys the sovereign, but he does not obey anyone else.

What is command?
For something to be a command, it has to be backed by threat of sanction and should be given by the sovereign. The ideas of sovereign and sanctions distinguish command from other statements. In case of its violation, evil is to be imposed. Duty arises from sanction. The magnitude of sanction does not matter; it is the threat that brings obedience to law.[3]

Advantages of the command theory
·    Emphasises the posited nature of law.
·    Emphasises the source-based test for identifying the valid law. Law is law because it is issued by the sovereign commander. The merits of the command do not matter.
·    Command theory emphasises the coercive nature of law. Command theory proposes that threat of sanction is central to the law.  
·    Positivists are less concerned with the contingent feature of law. It is a contingent feature of UK law that it is backed by sanction. This theory is rooted in UK’s form of government.
·    Command theory also gives us some idea about the beginning of the legal system. Many legal theorists argue that law does not come in parts, rather it depends on a system. If we can identify the sovereign, we have a legal system.

Difficulties of the Command Theory

Hart criticizes the command theory in The Concept of Law. He presents the problem of Rex I and Rex II. After the death of Rex I, Rex II issues ten laws. He argued that how are the laws of Rex II laws in connection with the commands of Rex I? Hart identifies two problems with this theory, namely:

Continuity problem: Why does law exist already? We have yet to see whether people habitually obey Rex II. Rex I is dead, and it is inappropriate to assume that people still obey Rex I. If the conception of habit of obedience is such an indispensable ingredient for constituting a ‘sovereign’, then authority of succession of Rex II cannot be explained because the habit of obedience of population was for Rex I, not for Rex II, and habits do not develop in a day or two. Hart argues that we do know that systems continue after the deaths of sovereigns and dissolution of parliaments. The command theory does not explain how laws continue to apply. Hence, he says that the command theory is too simplistic.

Persistence of Law: Command theory also fails to explain the persistence of certain laws. In R v Duncan (1944) a woman was prosecuted in England and convicted for telling fortunes in violation of the Witchcraft Act 1735. Why did this law persist? How can a statute enacted three centuries ago still be a good law? Hart argues that the law persists not because of the habitual obedience of society, but because it was enacted by the parliament and was never repealed.

Hart’s alternative: legal systems as the union of primary and secondary rules

Hart describes law as a union of primary and secondary rules. The primary rules impose duties and the secondary rules confer powers. There are three types of secondary rules: rules of change; rules of recognition; and rules of adjudication. For Hart, the combination of primary and secondary rules is the key to the understanding of jurisprudence.

Why do we need primary and secondary rules?

Primary rules are those which impose duties and obligations and impose sanctions. With primary rules alone, a society cannot work for long. A society that only has primary rules is a primitive society. In Hart’s conception, such a society is bound to face the problems of uncertainty, inefficiency and static nature of the laws. Therefore, to bring the society out of this primitive stage, the primary rules should be unified with the secondary rules (rule of change, rule of recognition and rule of adjudication).

Rule of Recognition: the main function of the Rule of Recognition is to identify whether another rule is part of the legal system or not. It provides the standard of validity of other rules in a legal system. Rule of Recognition is the authoritative criterion for identifying primary rules of obligation. This criterion may take any one or more of the variety of forms: meaning that they may include reference to authoritative text; to legislative enactment; to customary practice; to general declarations of specified persons, or to past judicial decisions in particular cases. Rule of Recognition is not universal; it only signifies when something would be called as law.

How do we identify the rule of recognition? Where does it come from?

It is a social fact or an official practice. Hart answers it through an analogy with the standard of meter. For Hart, it does not matter where it comes from. All we need is an objectively identifiable standard/measuring meter to tell what law is and what is not. For Hart, “Rule of Recognition is inherently objective.”

If a woman goes for abortion, the officials will recognise her right under the law. Why does the Abortion Act 1967 hold the value of being a law? Under Hart’s conception, any legislative exercise can be described in the following words: anything passed through a prescribed legislative process within the bounds of the enforced constitution would be declared as law. Thus, the process enforced by the constitution validating the laws passed through it is the Rule of Recognition and is the reason why the Abortion Act 1967 is considered as a law.

Can the union of primary and secondary rules solve the difficulties of continuity and persistence?

We have the mechanism to know the validity of law through the rule of recognition. The secondary rules keep the system persistent. The rule of recognition keeps the system going. It does not matter who controls the parliament. All these secondary rules have to work together to exist. Impersonal rules keep the system going. Legal system can regulate its own creation under the secondary rules.

Hans Kelsen: Legal systems as chains of validity unified by the Grundnorm

The validity of a legal rule can be traced back to the basic norm or grundnorm. What justifies the act of traffic warning for ticketing a person’s car? If the traffic warden tickets your car for wrong parking, you can trace the roots of his authority to a higher norm.

What is Grundnorm?
Historically first constitution is the grundnorm. It is a juristic presupposition. We have to presuppose the first norm. That basic norm is not man-made. “The historically first constitution ought to be obeyed” is the grundnorm of the constitution because legal system will collapse if it is not obeyed. It is a pyramidical structure of validation. Law is law because of the social practice of officials. For Kelsen, this is not the social fact, but a presupposition. Kelsen had the ambition of giving a Pure Theory of Law, which is independent of sociology or political science.

The Internal Aspect of Law

(1) Rules in The Concept of Law, or how Bentham and Austin failed to understand law from the point of view of those who are subject to it and use it in guiding their conduct.

The command theory describes law as a command of sovereign who is habitually obeyed by the population. Hart claims that the command theory presents law from an external point of view only. It means that when the order is backed by an external threat of sanction, obedience would be rendered by the people. It is a predictive aspect of the account i.e. if command is broken, sanction follows.

(2) An Introduction to the Principles of Martian Sociology: what is the mistake which is made by the external observer at the traffic lights—what does he miss? (Reading: Hart, The Concept of Law, 55-61 and *88-91)

Example of following traffic rules observed by someone who comes from Mars: If red light is on, people stop. If they do not, the police charge them. This is not an untrue account, but it is missing something important. This is only a partial account. We know that people in cars take red light as a signal and reason to stop. They know that there is a rule which requires them to stop.

Hart says that we are missing an important thing, that is, human beings are aware about rules. He calls this a critical reflective attitude towards rules. Hart says that an alien is missing the whole dimension of normativity—what we ought to do. People may have different reasons for obeying the law. If we internalise the value of rule, we will not follow it out of compulsion. The person indulges in a critical reflective attitude. The reason for stopping himself from doing something is because he himself believes that it is wrong. This is what Hart thinks is the internal aspect of law. In short, people do not necessarily abide by the law because of the threat of sanction. Sometimes, it is the critical reflective attitude of the people that identifies a value in following a particular act because of it being inherently good.

Understanding why the external observer makes the mistake which he does.

Why is it missed?
The Martian did not ask the people in cars that why do they stop. This theory misses the account of those who are subject to law. Hart thinks that law is a system of guidance for human conduct. According to him, this is scandalous to miss the views of the subjects of law. You miss out the key to the phenomenon you are observing if you do not ask the people that why they are obeying the law.

Habits and Rules reconsidered

This leads Hart to draw a distinction between habits and rules. We need to differentiate between habit governing and rule following behaviour.

There are certain differences, primarily three indicators which are:
·      Deviation from rules, but not habits, are open to criticism.
·      Deviation from the standard is regarded as a good reason for the criticism.
·      There is an internal aspect of rules—at least some people regard the rule ‘from the inside’ i.e as a standard to be followed, as something which ought to be done. Characteristic use of normative language—ought, right, should, etc.

For example, there are two bus stops and I usually take a bus from one bus stop. But one day I want to have a change and go to the other bus stop. This will not make me subject to criticism. I will not criticise myself for this as well (internal aspect). In another scenario, if I am required to teach and do not turn up for teaching, then I will be subjected to criticism. There is a reason for criticism because I have a contract to turn up for teaching. This contract provides a rule.

The internal point of view and the union of primary and secondary rules

Where does the internal-external aspect of law fit in?

We have already given part of the answer while discussing Hart’s criticism of external view. The views of subjects (who obey law) are missing here.

Primary rules are conduct governing rules while secondary rules deal with change, adjudication and recognition. Secondary rules are directed towards officials. Hence, there are two minimum conditions, necessary and sufficient, for the existence of a legal system. These are:

(1) Rules of behaviour, which are valid according to the system’s ultimate criteria of validity, must be generally obeyed.

(2) Secondary rules of change, adjudication and recognition must be accepted by the officials of the system from the internal point of view.

Official acceptance from the internal point of view means an acceptance that the secondary rules set a standard which ought to be followed—common standards of official behaviour which they uphold and criticise deviations in their own and others conduct. These are the officials who should have this internal aspect of the point of view. If a judge accepts a certain rule, he will criticise any deviation from it.

However, it is not necessary that officials accept the rule as a morally good thing. As a judge, you do not need to believe that it is good to have rules. You may have so many reasons to be a judge. A judge can be an anarchist. So long as a judge performs his duties, there is no problem. Hart considers himself to be a realist. He thinks that as long as some civil servants who write the laws obey them even if they do not believe in them, there is no problem.

Hans Kelsen’s Pure Theory of Law, and the role of the basic norm, or Grundnorm, in explaining the normativity of law

Kelsen's Pure Theory of law is pure from morality and sociology. The theory is pure because it separates jurisprudence from other disciplines like ethics, politics, and psychology. It is a pure legal science because it has its own methodology. For him, the explanation of law’s internal aspect, or its normativity, lies not in the attitudes of those who are subjected to the law. Kelsen explains pure social facts. He does not want to look into the normativity of law.

Grundnorm:

For Kelsen, every law is legitimized by the other law. This hierarchy of laws narrows down as we go up till we reach the Grundnorm, which legitimizes other laws underneath it. Grundnorm or the basic norm is a presupposition. The Basic Norm is not posited, rather it is presupposed. Hence, the basic norm is assumed to be valid. The Grundnorm is not a rule of recognition. The presupposition is that the historically first constitution ought to be followed (that coercive acts ought to be carried out under the conditions which the historically first constitution and the norms created according to it prescribe). There is a necessity of presupposing the basic norm if we are to understand legal system as creating valid norms or guides to conduct.

Some key points as to the concept of Grundnorm:

ð Grundnorm: The historically first constitution ought to be obeyed. à The grundnorm of the constitutional system. (Presupposition).
ð The concept of Grundnorm is fictional; it is not man-made. The validity of Grundnorm is dependent upon its efficacy. If people do not believe in it, the legal system may collapse.
ð Revolutions may change the Grundnorm as result the previously existing Grundnorm (always an ought to be statement) becomes inefficacious.
ð Two Grundnorms cannot exist simultaneously.
What does it mean to presuppose the basic norm, and can legal theory do this, whilst still remaining ‘pure’?

Tension with legal positivism

Raz provides one explanation of Kelsen’s theory. Think of a hypothetical man who only accepts the legal system and its rules. This man presupposes the norms. He thinks that these norms ought to be obeyed. Raz argues that, in order to understand the pure theory, this hypothetical man has to presuppose everything. Raz calls this ‘justified normativity’. This is contradictory.

Resolving the tension

A professional and uncommitted sense of adopting or presupposing the basic norm – statements from a point of view – the point of view of the legal system/hypothetical legal man.

Raz thinks that there may be a professional attitude towards norms without being a hypothetical legal man. You can detach yourself from the legal system. Imagine two friends. One is Catholic and the other is Orthodox Jew. Catholic friend is an expert on Rabbinical law. He can guide his Jewish friend regarding Rabbinical law. But he makes detached statements. He does not believe in Judaism.

Legal philosophy has to presuppose the basic norm without going to the system. For example, a radical immigration lawyer who does not believe in the immigration system but advises according to the laws can completely detach himself from his views while conducting his profession.

Hart’s Criticism:

Kelsen reduces everything into a formula, hence it obscures the social functions of law. Hart gives example of two laws which have very different social functions, however, when they are laid down in Kelsen’s formulas, they look exactly the same. Hence, there is a flaw in Kelsen’s theory. These examples are:

Fine to be paid if taxes are not paid. In Kelsen’s formula: “If you don’t pay taxes, you ought to pay fine.”
Buy a Ferrari and pay 50% tax. In Kelsen’s formula: “If you buy Ferrari, you ought to pay 50% tax.”

At some place, the purpose of taxation is just to reduce the occurrence of an activity while at other is to generate some revenue. Similarly, the purpose of fines may also vary from situation to situation.

Two statements:
1- “If one imports alcohol, one ought to pay custom duty equal to the price.” 2- “If one imports alcohol, it ought to be confiscated and heavy fine be imposed.”

These two statements are identical, but theory is inadequate to recognize the different purposes that they satisfy. These are identical as they both are the directions to the official. But these varying purposes are obscured in the description of Kelsen’s theory.

Hart says that this non-distinction is absurd. Law is not just about sanctions. Kelsen’s interpretation of law diminishes the social functions of law which include guiding behaviour and coordination of human activities. According to Hart, Kelsen’s theory only works in a court room.

3. Legal Anti-Positivism: The Critique of Positivism

Criticism of Hart’s theory in Dworkin’s famous paper ‘Model of Rules’

A. The three central tenets of positivism:

a)     The law is a set of rules, and these rules are identified by their pedigree, rather than their contents. Their status does not depend on their contents.
b)    Law is made up of only these rules. Valid rules are exhaustive. It follows that where a case is not covered by these rules, then officials deciding the case have to apply their discretion beyond the law. Raz called this ‘unregulated’ disputes, where rules do not apply.
c)     To have a legal obligation is for one’s case to fall under a valid rule. Where there is no valid rule, there is no obligation. In these kinds of situations, there is retroactive creation of obligation.

B. Dworkin argues that this theory leaves out many things which we know about our legal system. For instance, it leaves out principles like ‘no one should benefit from one’s own wrong’. There are some hard cases in which rule of recognition cannot provide guidance. In these types of cases, judges apply principles – which are beyond the legal rules – to decide cases. Hence, law is not simply rules, but there are also principles which come from the morality of community and political standards. These principles are as important as the rules, but they do not derive their validity from rule of recognition. Hence, Dworkin argues for a distinction between the rules and the principles.

Rules v Principles

Rules apply in all or nothing manner. For example, the requirement of three witnesses for the validity of a will. You make the rule more and more elaborate in order to make it clear what to cover and what not to cover. They are binding because they must be used and considered. In case, the rules are not followed the action might not be legally recognized. For instance, if the requirement of three witnesses is not followed strictly, the will would not hold any legal force.

Same is not true regarding principles. For instance, there is a principle that ‘no one should benefit from one’s own wrong.’ But in many instances people do legally benefit from their own legal wrongs. For example, it has long been an accepted law that trespass gives legal rights through adverse possession.

Principles have a dimension of ‘weight’ or ‘importance’, whereas rules do not. If there are two conflicting rules, then they have to be reconciled. On the other hand, if two principles conflict, then both remain relevant, but the important one prevails because it is more important in that situation. However, we can also say that the reason one rule is exception to the other is because we consider one to be more important. One legal rule may be more important than another because it has a greater or more important role in regulating behavior. When principles intersect (the policy of protecting automobile consumers intersecting with principles of freedom of contract), one who must resolve the conflict has to take into account the relative weight of each.

Dworkin clarifies that sometimes a rule and a principle can play much the same role, and the difference between them is almost a matter of form alone.

B.    There are situations which are not covered by the existing authorities. You have to make legal arguments in order to decide the case one way or the other. A good legal argument persuades the court. Legal argument has a distinctive form to it.

Two hard cases:
In Riggs v Palmer, a young man knew this father made a will to give his property to him. He used a shortcut and murdered his father to get property. There was no restriction that could prevent giving effect to the will. However, there was a question before the court whether to allow it. The court said that this person cannot inherit it. Hence, they made a principle that no person can benefit from his own wrong.

Similarly, in Hemmingsen v Bloomfield Motor, a car manufacturer was selling his car. He signed a contract excluding his liability for defects in car manufacturing. The man went to the court and sued the car manufacturer. The car manufacturer brought the contract in front of the court. Rules in this case would find the contract valid. However, the court did not follow this. The judge developed a new principle and held the car manufacturer liable.

Positivists are committed to the idea that where there is no rule applying to a case, officials have a discretion to decide the case unconstrained by other legal standards (such as principles). But what is discretion?

Nature of discretion
There are, at least, two senses of discretion:

1.     Where the application of the standard requires judgment on the part of the decision-maker (for example who is the most experienced person to undertake a particular job);
2.     Where the decision of an official cannot be reviewed by another official (for example refusal of leave to appeal applications).

In both cases, it does not mean that there are no standards to be followed. Even though courts can overrule their decisions, it does not mean that they are not guided by some legal standards. When considering overruling an earlier decision, the court weighs up competing principles. If this was not the case, then precedents would not be binding.

Judges must have discretion, but does it mean that they can do anything? The main criticism is that judges are not elected representatives. If they start acting as deputy legislators, then it will be inherently undemocratic. Also, if judges are allowed to exercise discretion, they would be legislating retrospectively. To these criticisms, Dworkin responds that judges can only make decisions based on principles. They do not know laws involving policy making. They only need to look at established past precedents and legal principles to meet the requirements of “justice or fairness or some other dimension of morality”.[4] This does not mean that they are acting undemocratically. Through precedent, they establish such principles and do not create a new duty/right.

C.     Is this a supplement to Hartian account of law?

Dworkin argues that legal principles cannot be accommodated under the Rule of Recognition. Therefore, the Rule of Recognition is not a litmus test to distinguish between law and non-law.

The problem with principles is that they do not have a pedigree, they might have an ‘institutional support’. The pre-existing rules of an institution anchor the decisions within that framework. The origin of these legal principles lies not in a particular decision of some legislature or court, but in a sense of appropriateness developed in the profession and the public over time. Their continued power depends upon this sense of appropriateness being sustained. We could not devise any formula for testing how much and what kind of institutional support is necessary to make a principle a legal principle, still less to fix its weight at a particular order of magnitude.[5] 

A legal principle must have some grounding. There must be something in the existing legal system that exemplifies this principle. Dworkin argues that the institutional support is not there for legal principles. Some legal principles might be very popular at one point in time. For instance, in the nineteenth century, in tort law, there was a principle of no liability without fault. But it changed later when the principle of strict liability was introduced in Rylands v Fletcher in 1868.

Legal principles are the stock in trade for justifying legal decisions. You cannot ground legal principles in the doctrine of precedents.

Cases matter and the use of principles in cases is important, but these principles do not set a precedent. This is a challenge that Dworkin presents. He argues that the positivist theory of law is not simply incomplete, rather it is misguided. 

How might a positivist respond to this argument?

Hart critiques Dworkin’s theory of interpretation on two counts, particularly relating to the idea of principles in relation to the rule of recognition. It was supposed to be a two-part essay, but Hart died before he could write the second part.

1.      Dworkin is mistaken on two points: (i) that the Rule of Recognition only validates rules, rather than general standards (including principles). There is nothing special for rules. When rules are mentioned, it means standards. Kelsen uses the term norm for them. There is nothing special in the use of ‘rules’. There is no reason why the Rule of Recognition has to be conceived in a restrictive sense. (ii) That the Rule of Recognition must use pedigree tests for identification, rather than test based on content (eg analogy to the doctrine of ultra vires). In Hart’s words, Dworkin’s ‘preoccupation with constructive interpretation’ has led him into a ‘double error’: first, to the belief that legal principles cannot be identified by their pedigree, and secondly to the belief that a rule of recognition can only provide pedigree criteria. Both these beliefs are mistaken; the first is so because there is nothing in the non-conclusive character of principles nor in their other features to preclude their identification by pedigree criteria.[6]

But there are two other concerns lurking in Dworkin’s argument:

(a)    A principle is a standard that is to be observed. Legal standards are worthwhile to be observed. They are desirable. They are not arbitrary, e.g., a will must have two witnesses. Why not three?

If legal principles are based on morality or overlap with them, does this mean that the standard to be used to identify them have to be moral? One argument is that if this is the case, then it would lead to uncertainty. Hart says that there is no problem if moral criterion is used. It does not matter that what criterion the officials use. Hart uses inclusive positivism. The opposite is exclusive positivism, which Raz uses.

(b)   If principles are identified by some criteria, what is that criteria? Anyone who wants to defend Hart must answer this question.

2.      Dworkin is right in stating that the Rule of Recognition cannot accommodate legal principles, but that merely requires a modification, rather than a rejection of the positivist view of law.

Legal standard covers (i) rules identified by the Rule of Recognition, valid legal rules. Valid norm is one that ought to be obeyed. Kelsen has a distinctive account of law. Raz synthesises Hart and Kelsen. He combines Hart’s view with Kelsen’s idea of normativity. He combines it with the idea of authority. (ii) The idea here is that there are other standards accepted by officials as binding on them in determining legal rights and duties. The Rule of Recognition is simply accepted by officials. The officials have an internal point of view, a critical reflective attitude towards law.[7] 

All officials accept that statutes are law. But even this is not uncontroversial. Dworkin argues that there is a type of consensus, but it is not the type Hart mentions. If something is judicial custom, how can an individual judge deny this? It makes it very unclear that how legal principle operates. 

4. Legal Anti-Positivism: Hard Cases

Dworkin’s Law’s Empire — the view termed as interpretivism

For Dworkin, law is an interpretative process. It is an interpretation whose end goal is to show the law in its best light. Dworkin’s ‘Hard cases’ is a long and interesting article. It is a prelude to his book the ‘Law’s Empire’.

Hard case is a difficult case which is not covered by the law. In hard cases, the law is unclear, controversial or unsettled. One way to resolve a hard case is to provide a theory of adjudication. How to apply the law? Theory of law provides the material and theory of adjudication guides how that material is applied. Dworkin argues that this is an artificial distinction. At the end of the day, you have to think about how to apply the law.

A.    Dworkin states that where there is a hard case, judges act as deputy legislators. This action is in substance and not in style.

B.     It is important to distinguish between two types of arguments supporting a political decision. Political decision is a decision by a political institution. These two types of arguments are: (i) Argument of policy, e.g., improving national defence or improving environment, and (ii) Argument of principles, which involves respecting or securing individual rights.

Legislature will use both types of arguments. If courts were deputy legislators, then they should apply both types of arguments. But in hard cases, a decision is generated by arguments of principles, not by arguments of policy. Even the UK Supreme Court (before House of Lords) did not take decisions as a legislature does. However, judicial decisions in hard cases are not generated by arguments of policy, but by arguments of principle.

C.     Dworkin has three arguments in favour of this view of adjudication:

a)     Legitimacy: judges, unlike legislation, lack the democratic legitimacy to make law. Courts do not have legitimacy to make law. Therefore, their decisions should be based on principles, and not on policy arguments.
b)    Retroactivity: Judicial decisions are inherently retroactive. Decisions based on policy create new rights. That is why you cannot create them by a judicial decision retrospectively. Court decisions enforce people’s right while legislature creates new rights based on policy.
The above two arguments are based on political morality.
c)     Legal Practice: judges do not apply the law in hard cases as delegated legislators. They just argue about the appropriate legal considerations and how they should be resolved in the case before them until they reach a conclusion.

D.   Even in hard cases, courts try to apply the law in order to determine rights of parties. Now a legal right is an ‘institutional’ right—law is an institutional practice, and judges have to consider the character of the institution in making decisions.

Take an example of games. You have to accept the rules of the game to play it. For instance, chess is a game of intelligent skills. There might be other games of chance. You have to follow the rules of chess to play it. An umpire in cricket has to apply the rules of cricket to declare a player out irrespective his personal liking or disliking of a player. Similarly, judicial decisions must be consistent with the decisions in the past. Courts are not simply looking at the existing laws, they are looking into the principles that justify the existing laws.

Dworkin’s view shifts the focus on principles underneath the law. The focus of his theory is upon the principles which are applied in making judicial decisions.

E.     Dworkin argues that if you look at the common law reasoning, precedents have ‘gravitational force’. The precedents are taken to be relevant to situations that fall outside the direct scope of the decision. Why we choose some cases as similar to others? Treating like cases alike is acting in a way that is consistent in substance with acts in the past.

Law can be an interpretative process in the best way through its ‘integrity’. Law must have consistency; it should not be based on checkerboard solutions on whimsical basis. Law must speak with a single voice in a principled and coherent manner.

Ideally courts decide hard cases in terms of the existing law i.e. statutes and precedents. But some decisions are treated as anomalous which apply on their facts. This effectively means that such decisions are wrong.

Dworkin’s theory fits into the legal practice and justifies the practice. That is why it is desirable that decisions should be made in this way. The role of courts is to apply the law. Courts do that in a subtle way. Some decisions are wrong. Dworkin argues that his theory helps demarcate wrong decisions which are inconsistent.

F.     Dworkin goes further than merely giving a ‘theory of adjudication’ of ‘how courts do and should decide cases’. He introduces the figure of a superhuman judge—Hercules—who is able to decide cases unerringly considering the totality of law and exercising unerring moral judgment to reconcile principles. According to Dworkin, the law on some matter is what Hercules would conclude it is.


Criticisms

1.         Dworkin does not give the idea of law. In the end, it is merely a theory of adjudication because it provides no explanation for the identification of the institutional decisions on which it depends. Where does a rule of law come from? How do you explain the legal materials? Where does Hercules get this material from? How do we decide what is a statute or precedent? Theory of legislation and theory of adjudication are two different things.

2.         It is a general theory of law.  How does this theory apply on a legal system that is immoral, e.g., Nazi German or apartheid South Africa? This is not Dworkin’s problem; this is a problem with everyone. It is a challenge that what do you do if you come across some law as a lawyer or judge that is immoral, e.g., death penalty.

3.         It needs to be answered whether the actual law would be the same as the ideal law of Hercules?

5. The Natural Law Tradition

1. Natural law tradition emphasises that law has an inherently moral dimension.

Aquinas argued that a morally unjust law is not law. But we know as a matter of fact that many morally unjust laws are actual laws.

A good way to look at the natural law is to contrast it with positivist account of law. Law is a social and cultural practice. What distinguishes legal positivism is its assertion that law is exclusively a matter of social fact. Finnis would agree that law is a social practice but not a social fact. This leads to two derivative theses:

A.   The validity of individual laws depends upon their sources alone, not upon their merits. Please note that there are nuances within positivism such as inclusive and exclusive schools; and
B.    The nature of legal systems can be understood without attributing any intrinsic moral value, purpose, function or point.

Rejection of (A) is described as anti-positivism: Dworkin’s interpretivism is described as anti-positivism. Rejection of (B) is natural law.

2. Objections to the idea that law could be linked to morality

Objection 1

Does it not depend upon the content of the legal system that some laws are good while others are bad? You may say that law and morality are linked except in a contingent way. There is no inherent link but a contingent one. Sometimes they overlap and other times they do not. The aim of law could be to achieve some morally valuable end, e.g., to promote the common good of the community, even if all legal systems fall short of this.

It is not simply the content of legal system that matters. There are some intrinsic points which are morally desirable. Does the law have some basic moral functions? Legal positivists claim that law is a complex system. Think about a hospital. It is a complex. There are many people who work there. It is a complex social organisation. Its function is to alleviate ill health and disease. It is not simply a complex organisation. It has a function and you cannot understand it unless you understand its function. At some hospitals, there is a wide scale corruption. The function of a hospital is morally desirable. Similarly, it is not merely a question of content of law when we describe a legal system. You have to ask what is the function of law?

Objection 2

Morality is a matter of opinion, but law is a social practice. How can they be linked?

I. Morality is not just a matter of opinion. Bentham, Finnis and Gardner do not think that morality is simply a matter of opinion. Raz is a moral pluralist. Not everything that exists has an empirical realty. Take the example of promises. If morality is a matter of opinion, then promise has no value.

II. Even if morality were just a matter of opinion, this does not exclude there being a conceptual link between law and morality.

3. There are also negative points. What is the positive reason for thinking about some connection?

Firstly, there is a shared vocabulary. We talk about moral rights and moral wrongs. You do not find this similarity with other phenomenon such as language. We do not say that you have a duty to follow grammatical rules. Secondly, there is a common content between law and morality. Thirdly, there is centrality of justice. Both law and morality regard justice as the central point.

It is commonplace in legal systems that officials assert that everyone is morally obligated to obey the law, whether or not they agree with its content.

4. The function of law

Legal positivists claim that there are various functions of law, such as it regulates behaviour, provides facilities for private arrangement, resolves disputes and channels resources. The overriding function is guidance of human conduct. This does not have an inherent moral value. Law is only an instrument to guide human conduct.

5. According to Finnis the basic function of law is to co-ordinate social conduct. For example, we have to choose which side of the road to drive: right or left? This is a ‘coordination problem’. Both options are equally good as long as everyone follows the same rule to drive either right- or left-hand side.

There are essentially two methods to achieve coordination, either by unanimity or authority. Unanimity is difficult to achieve. We need authority to impose choice of the majority. If you have a dissenting minority, they can easily wreck the authority. This is a common phenomenon in failed societies. You need authority in order to solve the coordination problem. Law helps resolving coordination problems like allocation of property rights. Therefore, law is the directive of a body with authority over an entire community.

Legal positivists agree with the above proposition. But mere fact that there is a coordination problem does not entail that something is morally desirable.

Finnis argues that coordination is necessary for the realization of ‘common good’ of the community:

1.     The common good, the good of life in community and the good of the members of the community, cannot be realised without coordinating the conduct of the members of the community.
2.     The only (practicable) way to resolve the co-ordination problems of a human society is through authority.
3.     Law is simply the decisions taken by an authority in pursuit of the community’s common good.
4.     The fact that intrinsic function of law is to achieve the co-ordination necessary for the common good to be realised explains the presumptive moral force of legal obligations.

When you put the problem of coordination with common good, you see how law fits in. The idea here is that pursuit of common good is the proper function of law. We have hospitals to heal sick and unhealthy. Similarly, the function of law is to pursue common good.

Finnis argues that we cannot state law without describing its purpose. According to him, purpose of law is objectively justifiable. Pursuit of law is a point in which one’s legal obligation becomes a moral obligation. This is the focal point of law where the legal obligation equates with the moral obligation. Only at this point the society will be just because everyone will be conscious morally. It is the common good of society and it is an aspiration which the law should work towards.

Finnis agrees with Hart that law is a complex system. He contends that Hart’s theory of law presents an incomplete picture of law. In order to complete the picture, you need to understand that law exists to promote common good. Even the most corrupt states dress themselves up in these terms. They will claim that they are ruling for the good of the community.

Criticisms of Finnis’ Legal Theory

There are two obvious criticisms:
1. Is there anything as ‘common good’? Protection of individual rights might be more important; and
2. Finnis claims that the point and purpose of law is to promote common good. You may contend that the real purpose of law is to guide behaviour. Law is a form of social control and you hope that it will promote common good. But does the fact that law is necessary to promote common good show that the purpose of law is to promote common good? In other words, Finnis seems to deduce ‘ought’ from ‘is’.



[1] John Finnis, Natural Law and Natural Rights (2nd edn, OUP, 2011) 1.
[2] There is a diversity of opinions within legal positivists. Two main categories are inclusive and exclusive positivists with respect to their take on the relationship between law and morality. The former recognises the overlap between the two while the latter denies it.
[3] Bentham’s conception recognizes moral sanctions. Bentham and Austin had different ideas on sovereign. Bentham’s ideas are subtler than Austin and hence less prone to criticism.
[4] Dworkin, RM, ‘The Model of Rules’ (1967) 35 The University of Chicago Law Review 14, 23.
[5] Ibid, 41-42.
[6] HLA Hart, The Concept of Law (2nd edn OUP, 1997) Postscript 264.
[7] J Raz, ‘Legal Principles and the Limits of Law’ (1972) 81 The Yale Law Journal 823.

2 comments: